Monday, April 19, 2010

Wag the Tail

In his critic of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, as Henry Allison informs us in his account, Eberhard sets out to “recover [us] from the stupor induced by the Critique of Pure Reason” (Allison 16). He attempts to do so by providing a clear critique of the publication, which he mostly develops around on Leibnizian arguments. Allison outlines his arguments into four clearly delineated parts. Eberhard firsts critics Kant’s work on the limits of knowledge; secondly, he provides the justification of knowledge derived from non-sensible conditions; he then critics Kant’s argument about the nature of sensible conditions, namely space and time; and lastly, he questions the originality of Kant’s work as he likens it to a lesser version of Leibniz’s philosophy (Allison 16). In his first argument, Eberhard claims knowledge cannot be simply limited to sensible conditions as intuitive knowledge. In other words, there is another “purely, rational non-intuitive knowledge about […] things in themselves” (Allison 17). This, of course, Kant argued against, for, according to him, we can only have knowledge about things as they are given to us in experience within the sensible conditions of space and time. Any claims about anything else outside of experience equate to stretching the bounds of our understanding beyond its grasp. Eberhard explains that this limitation cannot be carried out since we can make claims about super-sensible things that are consistent with themselves but also comply with the nature of reality. He asserts the Leibnizian argument that as compliant with the basic human principles, namely sufficient reason and the principle of non-contradiction, the “transcendental validity” (which would equate to Kant’s term, “objective reality”) of such claims stands (Allison 17). As such, anything “that follows logically from these principles” (Allison 17) contains truth. The validity of claims is dependent only on the parameters of these principles, not dependent on their pertaining to the sensible conditions of knowledge. From this view, he argues that doubting any claims made by reason would lead to skepticism. Truth, for Eberhard, is “ the agreement […] with the necessary laws of reason and the understanding” (Allison 18). Under this definition, doubting claims made by reason outside of the sensible conditions would deprive us of any certain truth. For Eberhard, as long as something complies with the principle of non-contradiction and providing sufficient reason can provide logical knowledge outside of sensible conditions. Yet, Kant is not leading us into skepticism. He is not challenging the logic of such principle, if anything he asserts within experience. What he is challenging is the extension of these principles beyond their realm. His critique of Leibnizian rationalism derives from its presupposed “erroneous identification of our concepts of things with the things themselves” (Allison 21). Eberhard seems to ignore this and simply makes the same claim that principles that coincide with the nature of things as we experience them must hold validity outside of experience for the very same reason that they hold validity with experience. Simply because we cannot think of anything within our experience that could not escape the principle of non-contradiction does it mean that we can extend this principle to things outside of experience. Regardless of whether Kant succeeds in his quest to evaluate the validity of reason and its claims, Eberhard simply regresses from any progress Kant made by simply brushing off any challenges made to the presupposed validity of reason with the same justification that Kant challenges.

4 comments:

Sebastian Kolaj said...

Anuar, as you have implicitly stated in your post, the Copernican, or transcendental, Turn was simply too much for Eberhard to swallow. And, at first, I had felt the same as Eberhard, but, like you, I am gradually starting to see the method to Kant's madness.

Advocating the transcendental realism of Leibniz, Eberhard holds that our principles are not dependent on sensible experience, and that, instead, "reason [has] a content of its own" (Allison 17). This statement blatantly contrasts with the dependance that thoughts have on experience in Kant's CPR (CPR 193, B75). Personally, I think that Eberhard, and I suppose Leibniz as well, get knocked of their metaphysical feet by Hume when they then apply these so-called "non-intuitive" principles to experience (Allison 17). And thus, although he sacrifices the knowledge of things in themselves, Kant's notion of space and time as sensible intuitions of the mind is ultimately coherent from an epistomological standpoint. Otherwise, the gap between intellection and experience seems irreconciable.

However, I did find Eberhard's argument against Kant's way of using synthetic and analytic judgements compelling (Allison 42-43), viz., by learning more about something, is it not the case that a predicate becomes integral to a thing's definition? In otherwords, with our imperfect knowledge, where do we draw the line between a predicate and the actual property of a thing?

Anuar said...

Sebastian,

I agree with you in that Eberhard points a valid argument against Kant's view on and distinction of synthetic and analytic judgements. Once a predicate becomes so intrinsic to a thing, it would become hardly noticeable whether it is a predicate or a property of the thing. On the other hand, consider a predicate that applies to a particular. One might make a judgement of a particular thing, and eventually it could be the case that it becomes very hard to differentiate between a predicate between its properties, but it will always remain only pertinent to the particular. While a predicate may only apply to a particular, I think an actual property has a universal quality to it. As such, I think a distinction could be made.

Sebastian Kolaj said...

Anuar, I agree with you entirely. I do believe that there is a true distinction between a predicate and a property, and this allows for the possibility of analytical and synthetic judgements. Still, however, in a Kantian world where we must transcendentally apply our understanding to an essentially unintelligible manifold, it seems nearly impossible to locate where this line between predicate and property can be drawn. I almost think that a dogmatic approach to epistemology is necessary for there to be any talk about analytic judgements, mainly because such judgements are so assuming and based on empirical data. It seems as if Kant's world is solely fit for synthetic judgements, and that all we can do, from a transcendentally ideal standpoint, is predicate and synthesize, which feels rather uncomfortable, in a way.

Prof. Ashley Vaught said...

So do the differences between predicates and properties coincide with accidents and essences? I.e., the predicates would be accidents attaching to a subject--i.e., synthetic; and the properties would be essential characteristics of the subject--i.e. the object of an analytic judgment?

Good questions. I see the difference between essential and accidental predicates/properties, but I am not sure otherwise.